Quasi-realism

From Opasnet
Jump to: navigation, search


NOTE. Broken links refer to English Wikipedia.

Quasi-realism is the meta-ethical view which claims that:

  1. Ethical sentences do not express propositions.
  2. Instead, ethical sentences project emotional attitudes as though they were real properties.

This makes quasi-realism a form of non-cognitivism or expressivism.[1] Quasi-realism stands in opposition to other forms of non-cognitivism (such as emotivism and universal prescriptivism), as well as to all forms of cognitivism (including both and ethical subjectivism).

Simon Blackburn derived this stance [2] from a Humean account of the origin of our moral opinions, adapting Hume's genealogical account in the light of evolutionary game theory. To support his case, Blackburn has issued a challenge, Blackburn's Challenge,[3] to anyone who can explain how two situations can demand different ethical responses without referring to a difference in the situations themselves. Because this challenge is effectively unmeetable, Blackburn argues that there must be a realist component in our notions of ethics.

However, argues Blackburn, ethics cannot be entirely realist either, for this would not allow for phenomena such as the gradual development of ethical positions over time. In his 1998 book, Ruling Passions, Blackburn likens ethics to Neurath's boat, which can be changed plank by plank over time, but cannot be refitted all at once for risk of sinking. Similarly, Blackburn's theory can explain the co-existence of rival ethical theories, for example as a result of differing cultural traditions - his theory allows both to be legitimate, despite their mutual contradictions, without dismissing both views through relativism. Thus, Blackburn's theory of quasi-realism provides a coherent account of ethical pluralism. It also answers John Mackie's concerns, presented in his argument from queerness, about the apparently contradictory nature of ethics.

Quasi-realism, a meta-ethical approach, enables ethics based on actions, virtues and consequences to be reconciled.[4] Attempts have been made to derive from it a comprehensive theory of ethics, such as Iain King's quasi-utilitarianism.[5]

Criticisms

Despite gaining some of the better qualities of the component theories from which it is derived, quasi-realism also picks up vulnerabilities from these different components, too. Thus, it is criticised in some of the ways that moral realism is criticised, for example by fictionalism (see below); it is also attacked along with expressivism and other non-cognitive theories (indeed it has been regarded by some as a sub-category of expressivism).

Fictionalism

It has been claimed that Blackburn's programme is fictionalist[6], which he himself disputes. However, there are certainly continuities between both approaches. Blackburn argues that moral fictionalism is tantamount to us claiming to hold attitudes that we do not really have; that we are in some way insincere. In support of his argument, Blackburn invokes Locke's theory of colour, which defines colours as dispositional (that is, in the eye of the beholder) but in some way reliant upon facts about the world. Blackburn buttresses these arguments by further examples of quasi-realism in our understanding of the world beyond ethics.[7]

This means that, though the moral fictionalist is in some ways having cake and eating it, the quasi-realist has a seemingly even more difficult position to defend. They may feel secure in disagreeing with Bentham that talk of natural rights is "nonsense upon stilts" but they would also argue that such rights could not be said to exist in a realist sense. Quasi-realism captures in some important ways the structure of our ethical experience of the world and why we can assert claims such as "It is wrong to be cruel to children" as if they were facts even though they do not share the properties of facts; namely the inference of independent truth-values.

From this position, Blackburn's "way forward" is to re-assert Hume's 'common point of view', or the ethical discourse common to mankind. Blackburn's thought is that though relativists and realists can agree that certain statements are true within a certain discourse, a quasi-realist investigates why such discourses have the structures that they do.[8]

Frege–Geach problem

The coherence of Blackburn's quasi-realism has been challenged most notably by the Frege–Geach problem, which assert Blackburn's position is self-contradictory. Advocates of Blackburn's view, however, would contend that quasi-realism in fact provides an antidote to the Frege–Geach problem by placing different moral claims in context. There is an important difference, claim the quasi-realists, between saying It is wrong to tell lies, and It is wrong to get your brother to tell lies.[9] Indeed, say the quasi-realists, the Frege–Geach argument exposes the insensitivity of some moral realist discourse to the complexity of ethical statements.

See also

References

  1. Moral Anti-Realism > Projectivism and quasi-realism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
  2. Ruling Passions (1998) ISBN 0-19-824785-0.
  3. Essays in Quasi-Realism (1993). ISBN 0-19-508041-6.
  4. Template:Cite book The reference on page 116 of this book states: In How to Make Good Decisions and Be Right All the Time: Solving the Riddle of Right and Wrong, London: Continuum 2008, Iain King develops a quasi-utilitarian system compatible with consequence-, virtue- and act based ethics.
  5. How to Make Good Decisions and Be Right All the Time: Solving the Riddle of Right and Wrong, (2008), ISBN 978-1-84706-347-2, p. 187
  6. For example, by David Lewis, as cited in a 2006 edition of Analysis, accessible here
  7. Truth: A Guide (2005) ISBN 0-19-516824-0.
  8. Truth: A Guide (2005) ISBN 0-19-516824-0.
  9. Ruling Passions (1998) ISBN 0-19-824785-0.
Leo Lahti. B.Sc thesis (in Finnish). Simon Blackburnin kvasi-realismi ja moraalisen keskustelun turvaaminen / Concerning Blackburn’s quasi-realism in securing moral discussion. University of Helsinki, Faculty of political sciences, 2009. CC-BY license. [1]
  • Tuomas Akvinolainen (2002): Summa theologiae. Valikoiden suomentanut J.-P. Rentto. Gaudeamus, Helsinki, 2002.
  • Alfred J. Ayer (1936): Language, Truth, and Logic. (Toinen painos, 1946.). Gollancz, London.
  • Jeremy Bentham (1789): An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. T. Payne, London.
  • Isaiah Berlin (1998): The Proper Study of Mankind: An Anthology of Essays. Random House, Iso-Britannia.
  • Simon Blackburn (1984):. Spreading the Word. Clarendon, Oxford.
  • Simon Blackburn (1993): Essays in Quasi-Realism. Oxford University Press.
  • Simon Blackburn (1998): Ruling Passions. Clarendon, Oxford.
  • Simon Blackburn (1999): ”Is Objective Moral Justification Possible on a Quasi-Realist Foundation?”: Inquiry 42, 213–228.
  • Simon Blackburn (1996): ”Securing the nots”Teoksessa Walter Sinnot-Armstrong ja Mark Timmons (toim.), Moral knowledge?, Oxford University Press.
  • Rudolf Carnap (1937): Philosophy and Logical Syntax. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., London, 1937.
  • Terence Cuneo (2006): ”Saying what we Mean”. Teoksessa Russ Shafer-Landau (toim.): Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Oxford University Press.
  • Peter. T. Geach (1965): ”Assertion”. The Philosophical Review, 74, 449–465.
  • Allan Gibbard (1990): Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
  • Paul Boghossian (2006): ”What is relativism?”. Teoksessa P. Greenough ja M. Lynch, (toim.): Truth and realism, Oxford University Press.
  • Richard. M. Hare (1952): The Language of Morals, Clarendon, Oxford.
  • Terry Horgan ja Mark Timmons (2006): ”Cognitivist Expressivism”. Teoksessa Terry Horgan ja Mark Timmons (toim.): Metaethics after Moore, Oxford University Press.
  • Richard Joyce (2008): Projectivism and quasi-realism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Verkkoviite. Viitattu 30.4.2008. [2]
  • Immanuel Kant (1788): Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft. Alkuperäisteos julkaistu 1788.
  • Hugh LaFollette, (toim.) (2000): The Blackwell guide to ethical theory. Blackwell publishers ltd.
  • John. L. Mackie, (toim.) (1977): Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Pelican Books.
  • George. E. Moore (1903): Principia Ethica. Cambridge University Press, New York.
  • Thomas Nagel (1987): ”Fragmentation of value”. Teoksessa Christopher W. Gowans (toim.) Moral dilemmas, Oxford University Press.
  • Michael Ridge (2008): ”Moral non-naturalism”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Verkkoviite. Viitattu 29.4.2008. [3]
  • Mark van Roojen (2008): ”Moral cognitivism vs. non-cognitivism”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Verkkoviite. Viitattu 25.4.2008. [4]
  • Charles. L. Stevenson (1944): Ethics and Language, Yale University Press.
  • Chris Swoyer (2008); ”Relativism”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Verkkoviite. Viitattu 25.4.2008. [5]
  • Nicholas Unwin (1999): ”Quasi-realism, negation and the frege-geach problem”. The Philosophical Quarterly 49, 337-352.
  • David B. Wong (1984): Moral relativity. University of California press, London.
  • Hoayoung Youn (2005): Objective values and moral relativism. Väitäskirja, University of Texas at Austin.